Brian Frantz
Apologetics
11/20/03
Response to
Why I Am Not A Christian by Bertrand Russell:
Although I will grant
that some of the arguments Russell sets forth in this
writing are well-put, they are by no means incontrovertible
and are outnumbered by his patently false assumptions
and accusations regarding Christianity. The work begins
with Russell’s definition of a “Christian.”
It seems at first as though he is choosing the most
far-reaching and “fair” definition. However,
he says that he “shall not insist that a Christian
must believe in hell” (50). I would argue that
anyone who does not believe in hell is not a Christian,
for at the base of Christian theology is the fall.
Thus, some of the arguments Russell sets forth may
be refuted by the mere fact that he is assuming orthodox
Christianity can be exist without the hell and, consequently,
without the fall. This is his first problem.
Russell goes on to discuss
the classical arguments for God. The first comment
in this section that I found interesting was his reference
to having to wait “until Kingdom Come”
(50) – interesting choice of words for an anti-Christian.
Moving on, though, it is important to point out that
many Christians have pointed out the exact same difficulties
that Russell puts forth. The classical arguments serve
a purpose, but whether or not they survive scrutiny
does not determine whether God’s existence is
reasonable. Thus, Russell’s arguments may expose
true weaknesses in the classical arguments, but they
do not really endanger the concept of God’s
existence.
Nevertheless, these arguments
contain certain statements that warrant a response.
While Russell makes valid points about the first-cause
argument, I do not find his response completely satisfactory.
He behaves as though the question “who made
God?” is a total refutation. However, to assume
a pre-existent creator makes more sense than to assume
a pre-existent creation. Matter, though orderly, is
not intelligent. If one assumes that only matter is
pre-existent, he must still answer how that matter
ordered itself into the clearly designed universe
we live in today. To throw billions of years into
the equation so it has time to “happen”
on its own is much less plausible than to simply say
that it was created by a pre-existent, intelligent
being.
In the portion on the
natural-law argument, Russell says “We now find
that a great many things we thought were natural laws
are really human conventions” (51). Here he
defines natural laws as conventional, and therefore
they are always changing and cannot be used to unequivocally
prove anything. This is a problem for Russell, however,
for later he uses “ordinary laws of science”
(53) to make the point that everything tends toward
a state of decay (which is strange, for how could
the universe evolve in an orderly manner if it tends
to decay?). Russell’s main point in this section,
however, is similar to his moral argument later. He
says “if there were a reason for the laws which
God gave, then God himself was subject to law”
(52). Just as I will say later in my response to morality,
a response to this is that rather than God arbitrarily
defining law, God is law. God is orderliness, and
therefore He is neither an arbitrary definer of law,
nor defined by a larger concept of law. Rather, law
is part of his nature – God is the originator
of the concept itself.
Russell’s response
to the argument from design has problems as well.
He expects an omnipotent and omniscient God to be
able to do better than the “Ku Klux Klan or
the Fascists.” What he fails to mention is that
in Christian theology, God created the universe perfect.
There was no death, decay, or any such aspects of
“the ordinary laws of science.” How then
did evil and imperfection enter the world? God created
man in order to love him and for him to love God back,
but of what value is compulsory love? We were created
perfect, but we were also given the choice to love
God or to reject Him. By having this choice, those
who decide to follow God do so out of genuine love,
not because they were forced. It seems as though Russell
thinks God should have created robots that would be
unable to disobey God or to reject Him. And advocate
of “freethinking society,” this is an
odd position for him to take.
In this same discussion,
Russell goes on to directly criticize the Almighty.
“Do you think
that, if you were granted omnipotence and omniscience
and millions of years in which to perfect your world,
you could produce nothing better than the Ku Klux
Klan or the Fascists?” (52-53).
First of all, why does
he make the argument that God made nothing better
than the KKK? Naturally, he chooses an example of
man at his worst to point out all the “problems”
with God’s creation. But this is really a non-issue.
Whether he used the example of genocidal Adolf Hitler
or peace-loving Gandhi is really irrelevant. The main
idea is that Russell is forgetting the fact that in
orthodox Christianity, man fell as a result of choosing
to obey Satan. If Russell is going to argue against
Christianity, he cannot deny the existence of Satan
or hell. If there was no hell or Satan, there would
be no explanation for the imperfections in the world
and Russell would have a point. But the fact is that
Christian doctrine holds to the fact that all evil
is a result of man’s fall. Thus, if there’s
anyone Russell should be blaming for the KKK or Fascism,
it is Satan – not God.
Russell also addresses
the moral argument for deity.
“If you are quite
sure there is a difference between right and wrong,
then you are in this situation: Is that difference
due to God’s fiat or is it not? If it is due
to God’s fiat, then for God himself there
is no difference between right and wrong, and it
is no longer a significant statement to say that
God is good. If you are going to say, as some theologians
do, that God is good, you must then say that right
and wrong have some meaning which is independent
of God’s fiat, because God’s fiats are
good and not bad independently of the mere fact
that he made them.” (53).
In other words, if morality
is an arbitrary definition made by God, then he is
not under that code. But if God is good, then “goodness”
must have some meaning independent of God himself
(and thus be above Him). My response is that God is
the definition of goodness and morality. There is
no meaning of goodness independent from God, and goodness
was not an arbitrary creation of God – it is
his very nature and essence. Russell concludes this
argument with a hypothetical about the devil making
the world “when God was not looking” (54).
This is a contradictory statement for Russell to make.
Number one, it accepts the existence of the devil
(who is synonymous with hell), and therefore he has
broken the rule he laid out for himself that he would
not bring hell into the equation. And second, he has
already accepted the definition of “God”
as omniscient (52), so how could God be “not
looking” and miss something? He violates his
own definition for God.
After attacking the common
arguments for God’s existence, Russell moves
on to the topic of Christ. He begins by listing various
statements made by Jesus that he agrees with. He tries
to show how these are not even followed by Christians.
However, he is judging the efficacy of Christianity
itself by the performance of those who follow it.
True, it is sad that Christians do not live more like
they should, but he is committing a logical fallacy
when he takes what is true about the part and applies
it to the whole. In other cases, he merely takes the
quotes out of context. For example, “Judge not
lest ye be judged” is taken by him to mean that
courts are unbiblical. He ignores the other verses
in the Bible where judgment is validated and even
commanded (not to mention a frequent act of God).
Then, of course, he would argue that this is a contradiction,
despite the fact that said quote is not coming against
the treatment of criminals or sinners, but against
a judgmental attitude.
Though C.S. Lewis’
“liar, lunatic, or Lord” argument is not
inerrant, it may be used against Bertrand Russell.
After listing points where he respects Christ, Russell
then denies His deity and explains how he believes
Christ to be mistaken about the time of the Second
Coming, among other things. But how could Christ,
who was so vocal about His status as Son of God, be
such a blatant liar about that while being a “good
teacher?” And on the topic of Christ supposedly
being so unsure about the timing of the Second Coming,
this is actually biblical: Mark 13:32 says that the
time of the Second Coming is known only to the Father.
As for Christ supposedly believing that His return
would come soon, a millions years is “soon”
to an infinite being! The passages where Christ speaks
of not thinking about tomorrow merely mean that He
could return in the next minute or the next millennium
– we must merely be certain to be ready for
that time if it should come soon. Our primary concern
should be what are we doing today for God’s
Kingdom and that we are ready now if he should return
at this time.
Russell then ups the
ante as he depicts Christ as some inhuman animal who
delights in the suffering of men. To Russell, for
God to send people to hell is the sign of immorality.
As he seemed to indicate in “The Character of
Christ,” Russell apparently does not agree with
the concept of justice. He is appalled that God would
send those who reject him to everlasting punishment.
He thinks that hell-fire as a punishment for sin “is
a doctrine of cruelty” (56). So God shouldn’t
have the right to judge his own creation. Additionally,
Russell takes these “violent and cruel”
quotes about people going to hell to be threats, when
they are actually meant as wake-up calls. I couldn’t
help but noticing that Russell includes plenty of
quotes of Christ acting violent and cruel, but none
of his healing the sick, feeding the hungry, or commanding
people to love one another. Before speaking of the
consequences that will come to those who do not believe
in Christ, 2 Peter 3:9 says “The Lord is…
not wishing for any to perish but for all to come
to repentance.” Clearly, Russell overlooked
these many examples. He then points out some less
significant complaints, such as Christ causing the
fig tree to wither for not bearing out of season.
I’m not sure what translation he used for that
quote, but neither the KJV nor the NASB (both highly
literal translations) include anything about it not
yet being fig season.
Another misconception
Russell has about Christianity is that it is based
on emotion. He thinks that people accept Christianity
(and religion in general) because of the argument
that “Christianity makes men virtuous, so if
you attack it you must not want virtue to continue!”
Despite the fact that this is hardly the typical Christian’s
method of defending their faith, Russell moves on
to give examples of how evil Christianity has made
the world – even making the statement that “the
Christian religion…has been and still is the
principal enemy of moral progress in the world”
(57). In an entirely predictable fashion, he mentions
the Inquisition and the many witch trials as results
of Christianity, and therefore all of Christianity
must produce and promote evil. This is patently not
the case. Once again, Russell has taken a couple examples
and applied it to the rest of the Church. Though some
Christians have certainly behaved in completely immoral
ways in the past (and still do), the actions of those
who fail to follow the Bible should not be used to
denigrate the value of the teachings contained therein.
To make the claim, as
Russell does, that Science and humanism will bring
forth moral improvement is historically unproven.
The United States, which was founded by predominantly
Christian and God-fearing men, has become the most
prosperous, advanced, well-run country in history
and gives incredible amounts of food and aid to poor
counties. Yet Germany, under the secular, humanistic
Adolf Hitler, embarked on a mission to kill off the
“inferior” Jewish race in order to “make
the greater whole of humanity happier.” Great
Britain, which has a historically Christian background,
has continued to be a prosperous country that also
contributes greatly to world prosperity. The Soviet
Union, run by Marx-influenced, non-Christian communists,
was responsible for countless deaths and suffering.
Israel, a nation of God-fearing Jews, is an oasis
of freedom and prosperity in the midst of the war-torn
Middle East. Palestine, a direct opponent of anything
Judeo-Christian, is run by terrorists and suicide
bombers. Though evil actions have been done under
the name of “Christian,” practicing
Christians who follow Christ’s instruction have
done more good for the world than any other religion.
Missionaries help feed and nurture the poor in other
countries, while telling them in love the way to salvation.
Churches, when they do their job, give to their community,
making the world a better place. For every example
of evil done by Christians, there are many more of
those who have taken on the servant’s heart
and shown selfless love to their fellow man. A relativistic,
“whatever makes people happy,” approach
to morality has not improved the world but instead
has produced men like Hitler. The spread of Christianity,
however, has arguably done more for mankind than any
other philosophical or religious institution in the
history of the world.
|